The article below has struck a cord with me and not in a good way. There are sooo many experts that say IQ is something that is set in stone and largely genetic but I disagree. I think environment has a huge role in how intelligent we become!!!
I am beginning to think that experts (after years of being institutionalised in University) become a little set in their ways of thinking and are unable to 'see' any other way. Read the article below and tell me what you think.
By Christopher Ferguson
The idea of intelligence —that human beings possess, to
varying degrees, an innate and universal ability to learn—has taken a
beating in recent decades. Ever since Stephen J. Gould's
Mismeasurement of Man (Norton, 1981) and Howard Gardner's
Frames of Mind: The Theory of Multiple Intelligences
(Basic Books, 1983), the notion of a single intelligence entity,
typically called "g," has come under assault. That is unfortunate.
A number of scholars, including L.L. Thurstone and more recently
Robert J. Sternberg, have argued that intelligence has been defined too
narrowly. But Gardner, a professor of cognition and education at the
Harvard Graduate School of Education, who won a prestigious MacArthur
Foundation "genius award" in 1981, has had enormous influence,
particularly in our schools.
Briefly, he has posited that our intellectual abilities are divided
among at least eight abilities: verbal-linguistic, logical-mathematical,
visual-spatial, bodily-kinesthetic, naturalistic, musical,
interpersonal, and intrapersonal. The appealing elements of the theory
are numerous.
It's "cool," to start with: The list-like format has great attraction
for introductory psychology and education classes. It also seems to
jibe well with the common observation that individuals have particular
talents. More important, especially for education, it implicitly
(although perhaps unintentionally on Gardner's part) promises that each
child has strengths as well as weaknesses. With eight separate
intelligences, the odds seem good that every child will be intelligent
in one of those realms. After all, it's not called the theory of
multiple stupidities.
Multiple intelligences put every child on an equal footing, granting
the hope of identical value in an ostensible meritocracy. The theory
fits well with a number of the assumptions that have dominated
educational philosophy for years. The movements that took flower in the
mid-20th century have argued for the essential sameness of all healthy
human beings and for a policy of social justice that treats all people
the same. Above all, many educators have adhered to the social
construction of reality—the idea that redefining the way we treat
children will redefine their abilities and future successes. (Perhaps
that's what leads some parents to put their faith in "Baby Einstein"
videos: the hope that a little nurturing television will send their kids
to Harvard.) It would be difficult to overestimate the influence of
Gardner's work, both in repudiating that elitist, unfair concept of "g"
and in guiding thought in psychology as it applies to education.
The only problem, with all respect to Gardner: There probably is just
a single intelligence or capacity to learn, not multiple ones devoted
to independent tasks. To varying degrees, some individuals have this
capacity, and others do not. To be sure, there is much debate about
Gardner's theory in the literature, with contenders for and against.
Nonetheless, empirical evidence has not been robust. While the theory
sounds nice (perhaps because it sounds nice), it is more intuitive than
empirical. In other words, the eight intelligences are based more on
philosophy than on data.
Of course, nothing is ever cut and dried when it comes to the social
sciences. Gardner and the psychologist Lynn Waterhouse engaged in a
lively debate in the journal
Educational Psychologist in 2006.
While the exchange was informative, empirical evidence to support
multiple intelligences was largely absent. As Waterhouse put it, the
theory is "persisting without adequate evidence"—and was likely to
continue to do so, she added, because of the "good news stories" it
provides. By contrast, a wealth of evidence supports the existence of
"g," which, contrary to the claims (or wishes) of some people, remains a
strong predictor of academic performance, job performance—particularly
in highly technical careers or those requiring decision making—and other
markers of "success."
Another issue with the theory of multiple intelligences is that too
many of the categories correlate too highly with one another to be
separate intelligences. Cognitive performance on skills related to
verbal-linguistic, logical-mathematical, and visual-spatial tasks, as
well as many memory tasks, tends to be highly related. In other words,
it goes back to "g."
The remaining intelligences have nothing to do with intelligence or
cognitive skills per se, but rather represent personal interests (for
example, musical represents an affinity for music; naturalistic, an
affinity for biology or geology) or personality traits (interpersonal or
intrapersonal skills, which correspond best to the related concept of
emotional intelligence). And even those interest areas may be enhanced
by "g." Only bodily-kinesthetic—the ability to manipulate one's own body
with dexterity—may truly represent a separate cognitive ability,
probably stemming from cerebellar activity involved in fine motor
control. It may be better represented as a neurophysiological trait than
as intelligence. Even for related activities—dancing, for
instance—having at least a modicum of "g" is still going to be necessary
to learn, say, complex dance choreography.
Finally, as Waterhouse noted in her exchange with Gardner, the theory
of multiple intelligences has little value for clinical testing of
intelligence or the prediction of future performance. "G" alone is
highly predictive of both academic and work success. The other
intelligences, or whatever they are, add very little.
Part of the confusion that has allowed the theory to survive long
past the stage of empirical disrepute is the irascible debate regarding
what intelligence is in the first place. Intelligence is among the most
stable of psychological constructs. It is as possible to define it both
operationally and conceptually as it is for almost any other
psychological variable, although that might not be saying much. At
worst, intelligence is like pornography: I may not be able to define it
to the satisfaction of all, but I sure know it when I see it (or, in the
case of intelligence, when I come across its absence). At the
optimistic extreme, a reasonable definition of intelligence is not hard
to come by. Intelligence: An innate cognitive ability that powers
learning. Perfect? No. But that's basically it.
Aren't there plenty of Ph.D.'s who can't fix their cars? Sure, but
the majority of them could learn if they were so inclined. An individual
with low "g" is going to struggle at both book learning and auto repair
(although perhaps car mechanics would prove more manageable than
literary theory or quantum physics). In other words, individuals high in
"g" are going to be able to learn a wider range of activities with
greater ease than individuals low in "g". The "g" that assisted our
hominid forebears in learning the skills of hunting, gathering, and
toolmaking is the same "g" that gives gifted/talented students an
advantage in calculus. Of course, one person can't learn everything, so
some folks pick, say, European history over Math Without Numbers (or
whatever the rage is in mathematics these days). The theory of multiple
intelligences fundamentally conflates intelligence and motivation. It's a
fatal flaw. Motivation is certainly important, and it works alongside
intelligence to produce results. However, having the raw biological
machinery of intelligence is simply irreplaceable.
Perhaps in a naïve effort to deny that inconvenient truth, the debate
about intelligence has become largely political, at times even
facetious. Intelligence certainly is not the only predictor of success
in work or in school, college, or scholarship, but it's as strong as
any. Unfortunately, it's also largely genetic. Social justice, treating
people the same, bringing out their best abilities are all worthy
ideals. Yet we must be cautious when ideals conflict with reality. The
world in which we live has no obligation to be politically correct. And
it is not politically correct to say that one person is, well, simply
more talented than another.
Despite some naysayers (think of Richard E. Nisbett's
Intelligence and How to Get It: Why Schools and Cultures Count,
published this year by Norton), evidence from behavioral-genetics
studies has long shown that environment plays a much smaller role than
inheritance in the development of intelligence. And that's defining
"environment" so broadly that it includes head injuries, infections like
encephalitis, malnourishment, and neglect. You've probably heard of
those studies of twins raised separately who show similar intellectual
abilities when reunited 50 years later. Many people like to think that
any child, with the proper nurturance, can blossom into some kind of
academic oak tree, tall and proud. It's just not so.
Multiple intelligences provides a kind of cover to preserve that
fable. "OK, little Jimmie may not be a rocket scientist, but he can
dance real well. Shouldn't that count equally in school and life?" No.
The great dancers of the Pleistocene foxtrotted their way into the
stomach of a saber-tooth tiger.
That is the root of the matter. Too many people have chosen to
believe in what they wish to be true rather than in what is true. In the
main, the motive is a pure one: to see every child as having equal
potential, or at the very least some potential. Intelligence is a
fundamentally meritocratic construct. There are winners and there are
losers. A relative doofus may live a comfortable life so long as his or
her parents are wealthy. However, clawing one's own way out of abject
poverty is best achieved with a healthy dose of both motivation and "g."
Naturally, we must be careful to avoid the fallacy that some people
deserve to live in poverty, or that entire groups of people are
inherently inferior in regard to intelligence. In the past, those
arguments have been used to support oppression, racism, and slavery, and
we must not repeat those mistakes.
Yet the belief that intelligence does not exist as a single,
reliable, important, genetically determined construct is an equal
fallacy. Unfortunately, some children and adults are just unintelligent.
It's not fair, it's not politically correct, but reality is under no
obligation to be either of those.
A pedagogy designed to identify strong and weak areas of achievement
is not a bad idea. But believing that such an approach rests on the
existence of multiple intelligences has real risks. It could lead us
down the path to intellectual relativism. Students encouraged to explore
their talents in dance or socializing may find themselves slammed
against a wall of reality when expected to actually know how to do
algebra or read a book in college. I'm not opposed to exploring those
talents (that's what recess and gym classes are for, and getting rid of
them has been a horrible idea), but national and international tests
indicate that we may be doing so to such an extent that we are
overwhelming our curricula.
Gardner's theory of multiple intelligences was a great idea and worth
investigating. It's just not panning out. Hanging on to the theory for
nostalgic or political value is not science. It's time that we begin to
work with the reality that we have, not the one we wish we had. To do
otherwise would be just plain stupid.
Christopher J. Ferguson has been promoted to
associate professor in the department of behavioral and applied
sciences, and criminal justice at Texas A&M International
University.